The Causal Structure of the World
notes by

F.C.T. Moore



If we wish to represent the world as a causal nexus, we may make a geometrical model: a space whose points represent events, and in which these points are linked by lines representing a causal connection.  Such a space is not Euclidean.  It will be a space which may be bounded or bent or discrete and which may have holes in it.  It may even have booby traps or oubliettes.  The Universe, considered as a causally ordered entity, might be a single land mass, or it might consist of a number of continents, perhaps tenuously connected.  There might peninsulae, islands and archipelagoes of causal structure, rather than the homogeneous nexus of which Kant cleanly dreamed.



One kind of "causal space", therefore, would mean that there is some causal path between any two events (just as in ordinary Euclidean space there is a line between any two points).  This seems to mean that we could never exclude in principle the existence of a causal connection between apparently unrelated kinds of event, though we might have good empirical reasons to exclude them.



A causal space of a Laplacean kind has strong characteristics:

The main claim is:

Since the state description is supposed to consist of statements about the position, mass and momentum of every elementary particle, Laplacean determinism, in this form, has an assumption:

These statements would enable one to infer future states of the universe provided that we have a general method of calculating the interactions of the particles described.  So there is a further assumption:

There is also a corollary.  If all future states of the universe are fully determined in this way, then pure physics would be enough.  Other sciences, or other ways of describing the universe, would be superfluous.  There arises the idea of "reductionism":



The last of these principles, "reductionism", is viewed by some as a metaphysical prejudice.  Thom writes (Structural Stability and Morphogenesis, pp. 158-9): "Contrary to what is generally believed about the two traditionally opposed theories of biology, vitalism and reductionism, it is the attitude of the reductionist that is metaphysical.  He postulates a reduction of living processes to pure physicochemistry, but such a reduction has never been experimentally established.  Vitalism, on the other hand, deals with a striking collection of facts about regulation and finality which cover almost all aspects of living activities, but it is discredited by its hollow terminology (e.g. Driesch's "organizing principle" and "entelechies"), a fault accepted and exaggerated by subsequent teleological philosophers (Bergson, Teilhard de Chardin).  We must not judge these thinkers too severely, however; their work contains many daring ideas that those who are hide-bound by mechanistic taboos can never glimpse ... The dispute is really pointless; many of the physicochemical properties of matter are still unknown, and realization of the ancient dream of the atomist - to reconstruct the universe and all its properties in one theory of combinations of elementary particles and their interactions - has scarcely been started (e.g. there is no satisfactory theory of the liquid state of matter).  If the biologist is to progress and understand living processes, he cannot wait until physics and chemistry can give him a complete theory of all local processes found in living matter ..."


GO BACK TO THE PAGE ON THE QUALITATIVE